To Carol
All Posts post a reply | post a new topic

AuthorTopic: To Carol
topic by
Seth Sims
4/19/2002 (23:05)
 reply top
Dear Seth: I try to have empathy for the plight of Israelis to the suicide bombers. I'm a very empathic person. I've always had Jewish friends in my life, tho half of them I would say were nuts. I can give you examples if you like.

I grew up in a divorced family and my father figure was a Iranian muslem married to a jewish woman. They eventually got divorced because she became a communist and he a socialist. My mother was Armenian and grew up in Istambul. She grew up with German Jews. Each person in my family at one time or another was in love with a Jewish person(????).I went to a very small high school and one third of the students were jewish. My first crush was on a Jewish boy.

My father figure, Mamoud, was a beautiful man, gentle, wise and intelligent. We would go on picnics with his cousins. Some of my best memories came from those outings. I have a muslim friend today. He is very americanized but devout in his religion and sends money regularly to Palestine. What is happening there now upsets him deeply. My real father taught syrian soldiers English during world war II. He loved the muslims and strangely enough his best friend is a muslim today..and two of his other best friends had been Jewish.

My only other contact with muslims comes from cab drivers. I took a cab about 15 years from the airport to my home. The cab driver was from the middle east. I knew within seconds of being in the cab that he hated me. It was also memorable for me because I had never before experienced that feeling anywhere else in America. I developed a kind of prejudice against cab drivers after that. Even after 9/11 I was wondering if the FBI had checked out the cab drivers. That kind of hatred is scary...because it creates an immediate wall with no hope of it breaking down.It was if it was written in stone for this man.

So I have had good and bad experiences with both Jews and Muslims. I was brought up with an automatic acceptance of Jewish people in my world. I don't know what is wrong with me at the moment.

I can't get myself to sympathize with Israel.I wrote out a complete story that I was going to post here where I took the point of view of an Israeli...it didn't work. I can't explain why to myself. Perhaps it has to do with power...and who has more of it. Perhaps if one of those cab drivers came after me I'd want to shoot him straight in the heart to protect myself. Maybe what they are going through in Israel is something you have to live through to understand.

What is happening in Palestine at the moment seems so much more real to me. What I would ask of you...for a moment...to step out of yourself...as I tried to do and failed...and say, Yes, this is wrong...this destruction in Palestine is wrong. Maybe you can't do it or maybe you won't do it. I would like to hear it...without any 'But...', without any back up of justification.

My latest 'bright idea' is for one or the other to let themselves be driven into the sea and to build a city there. It can be done.

reply by
carol
4/19/2002 (19:48)
reply top
That was my post..forgot to put my name in.

reply by
ozzie
4/19/2002 (20:11)
reply top
Well, let this cab driver (he being Muslim or Jewish - doesn't matter) come and take your home away, kill your family, and harrass you for the rest of your life.........will you become Ghandi? Will you lay down and pretend you're dead?

Throughout history, there has been many tresspassers on others, but there are those who tresspass and there are those who tresspass with an evil vengeance. I wouldn't say that the Palestinians have only been tresspassed against that's why I wouldn't expect them to become Ghandi!

reply by
Seth Sims
4/19/2002 (23:05)
reply top
Carol - The Israelis wanted the Palestinians to have their own state. They know that the Palestinians have been dealt a very bad hand. They know, I know, it is painful to live under occupation. But the Palestinians are more intent on killing Jews than they are on establishing their own state.
What are the Jews to do. They will eventually abandon most of the settlements, but only when they are confident that the Palestinians are ready to live in peace and not attack them.

It is natural to want to root for the underdog. But when the underdog is a frothing at the mouth pit bull, sometimes you can't fault the bigger dog for defending itself.

Sorry, I can't give you what you ask for. The destruction of a people is wrong, wanton destruction of towns is wrong, killing of innocents is wrong, BUT the Israelis are responding to terrorists that have and continue to target innocent civillians. The Israelis are not massacering people the way the Palestinian Propoganda machine would have you believe. You think the Israelis want that bad press?

What are the Israelis supposed to do? Accept having their people slaughtered?


Palestine will only get to be a state when it seeks peace and not destruction.

Amen

reply by
...IT'S THE OCCUPATION, STUPID !!!.
4/19/2002 (23:48)
 reply top
IT'S THE OCCUPATION, STUPID !!!.....STOP BEING A COLONIZER & STOP OPPRESSING people !!!... amnesty.org ...
reply by
carol
4/19/2002 (24:26)
 reply top
So the Israeli government isn't willing to in 'GOOD FAITH' give the land back to the palestinians without having their roads passing through and their checkpoints. This seems like a simple answer..a simple somewhat inexpensive trial...to give up the roads, give up the guards and checkpoints and see what happens. The whole world is watching now. Of course, this means going back to the 1948 agreement by the British. Will the palestinians accept that as kosher. Where will the settlements be resettled. Is that or has that become a political issue? So you give the land back and you get out. And you have independent surveyors hanging around. If without those checkpoints, etc...they gather together and get weapons and attack you...then the world will not wince if you attack back. The United States will support you without pussyfooting around...as will Britain, etc..and maybe the Arab states. Is this too simple?
reply by
watcher
4/20/2002 (8:38)
 reply top
You really don't know what the hell you are talking about, do you Lady?

What are you going to do when the Palestinians attack the Israelis from their new state?
Let Israel bomb them?
reply by
Wisso has your answer Carol
4/20/2002 (8:44)
 reply top
reply by
Wisso
4/20/2002 (2:46)
reply top

And barb....Jerusalem was occupied for MANY MANY MANY years b4 saladin liberated it....

dont worry bro..it all starts with a dream...that day u ll remember what good old 'extremist' wisso was saying......Israel has no futur...it s coming near it s end!!!

Everyone knows it....the futur is not with israel it s with arabs...arabs will win in long term... it may takes years.....but it will happen...

reply by
Wisso
4/20/2002 (2:53)
reply top
Who wouldve tought in 1942 that the hitler s german army would lose the war 3 years later?......As powerful as israel may seem....it doesnt take much for a country to collaps....

remmeber....Israel can make no mistake....1 mistake and it s gone!!!...gone forever!!!

reply by
Seth Sims
4/20/2002 (8:53)
 reply top
Hello Carol,

The Israelis will pull out of the West Bank and Gaza once the Palestinians have ceased trying to murder them and sign a serious peace accord that takes into consideration Israel's safety concerns. Wisso is correct in that there is no room for error.
How would you feel if you encouraged a police officer to put his gun down and then the criminal shot him dead?
That analogy is not so far from the situation in Israel. Only both the cop, the criminal, and the entire neighborhood will be destroyed.

Read this article by a University of Indiana Professor.

Israel's Survival and Nuclear War
9 May 2001


How shall Israel survive in a very bad neighborhood? Although this is an exceedingly complex question, we may safely assume that Israel's leadership will do whatever is necessary to preserve the state. This could include even the actual use of nuclear weapons.
Consider the following four distinct possibilities:

(1) NUCLEAR RETALIATION

Should an enemy state or alliance of enemy states launch a nuclear first-strike against Israel, Jerusalem would respond, assuredly and to whatever extent possible, with a nuclear retaliatory strike. If enemy first-strikes were to involve other forms of unconventional weapons, sometimes known as chemical or biological Weapons of Mass Destruction (WMD), Israel MIGHT launch a nuclear reprisal. This would depend, in large measure, upon Jerusalem's expectations of follow-on aggression and on its associated calculations of comparative damage-limitation. If Israel were to absorb a massive conventional attack, a nuclear retaliation could not be ruled out, especially if: (a) the Islamic state aggressors were perceived to hold nuclear and/or other unconventional weapons in reserve; and/or (b) Israel's leaders were to believe that non-nuclear retaliations could not prevent annihilation of the Third Temple Commonwealth. A nuclear retaliation by Israel could be ruled out only in circumstances where enemy state aggressions were clearly conventional, 'typical' (that is, consistent with previous instances of Arab/Islamic attacks in degree and intent) and hard-target directed (that is, directed towards Israeli weapons and military infrastructures rather than at civilian populations).

(2) NUCLEAR COUNTERRETALIATION

Should Israel feel compelled to preempt enemy state aggression with conventional weapons, the target state(s)' response would largely determine Jerusalem's next moves. If this response were in any way nuclear, Israel would doubtlessly turn to nuclear counterretaliation. If this retaliation were to involve other weapons of mass destruction, Israel might also feel pressed to take the escalatory initiative. Again, this would depend upon Jerusalem's judgments of enemy state intent and its calculations of essential damage-limitation. Should the enemy state response to Israel's preemption be limited to hard-target conventional strikes, it is most unlikely that the Jewish State would move on to nuclear counterretaliations. If, however, the enemy conventional retaliation were 'all-out' and directed toward Israeli civilian populations as well as to Israeli military targets, an Israeli nuclear counterretaliation could not be ruled out. It would appear that such a counterretaliation COULD be ruled out only if the enemy state's conventional retaliation were entirely proportionate to Israel's preemption; confined exclusively to Israeli military targets; circumscribed by the legal limits of 'military necessity;' and accompanied by explicit and verifiable assurances of non-escalatory intent.

(3) NUCLEAR PREEMPTION

It is EXTREMELY implausible that Israel would ever decide to launch a preemptive nuclear strike. Although circumstances could arise wherein such a strike would be perfectly rational, it is unlikely that Israel would ever allow itself to reach these dire circumstances. Moreover, unless the nuclear weapons involved were used in a fashion consistent with the laws of war, this form of preemption would clearly represent a most serious violation of international law. And even if such consistency were possible, the psychological/political impact on the entire world community would be negative and far-reaching. This means that an Israeli nuiclear preemption could be expected only: (a) where Israel's Arab/Islamic enemies had acquired nuclear and/or other weapons of mass destruction judged capable of annihilating the Jewish State; (b) where these enemies had made it clear that their intentions paralleled their capabilities; (c) where these enemies were believed ready to begin a 'countdown to launch;' and (d) where Jerusalem believed that Israeli non-nuclear preemptions could not achieve the needed minimum levels of damage-limnitation - that is, levels consistent with preserving the Third Temple Commonwealth.

(4) NUCLEAR WARFIGHTING

Should nuclear weapons ever be introduced into actual conflict between Israel and its many enemies, either by the Jewish State or by an Arab/Islamic foe, nuclear warfighting - at one level or another - would ensue. This would be true so long as: (a) enemy first-strikes against Israel would not destroy Jerusalem's second-strike nuclear capability; (b) enemy retaliations for an Israeli conventional preemption would not destroy Jerusalem's nuclear counterretaliatory capability; (c) Israeli preemptive strikes involving nuclear weapons would not destroy Arab/Islamic second-strike nuclear capabilities; and (d) Israeli retaliation for enemy conventional first-strikes would not destroy Arab/Islamic nuclear counterretaliatory capability. This means that in order to satisfy its essential survival requirements, Israel MUST now ensure the likelihood of (a) and (b) above, and the unlikelihood of (c) and (d). Looking over these four different scenarios that could lead Israel to actually use its nuclear weapons, Jerusalem will need to choose carefully between 'assured destruction' strategies and 'warfighting' strategies. My next essay will explore these critical strategic alternatives.



--------------------------------------------------------------------------------



Louis Rene Beres (Ph.D., Princeton, 1971), Professor, Department of Political Science, Purdue University, lectures and publishes widely on Israeli strategic matters. His work is well-known to Israel's military and academic communities. He is also the academic adviser at the Freeman Center for Strategic Studies, a Houston-based research facility and political action group.


reply by
Seth Sims
4/20/2002 (8:54)
 reply top
Israel's Survival And Nuclear War - Part 2
9 May 9, 2001


My previous essay dealt with four different scenarios that could result in an Israeli use of nuclear weapons. In this connection, Israel will need to choose prudently between what are professionally called 'assured destruction' strategies and 'nuclear warfighting' strategies. What follows is an informed exploration of these critical strategic alternatives. In the 'trade,' assured destruction strategies are also called 'countervalue' strategies or 'mutual assured destruction' (MAD). These are strategies of deterrence in which a country primarily targets its strategic weapons on the other side's civilian populations and/or its supporting civilian infrastructures. Nuclear warfighting strategies are also called 'counterforce' strategies. These are strategies of deterrence wherein a country primarily targets its strategic weapons on the other side's major weapon systems and its supporting military infrastructures.
For nuclear countries in general, and for Israel in particular, there are very serious survival implications for choosing one strategy over the other, although it is also possible that a country would opt for some sort of 'mixed' (countervalue/counterforce) strategy. Moreover, whatever deterrence strategy a country might choose, what really matters is what an enemy country PERCEIVES. In strategic matters, as in so much of life in all other spheres, the only pertinent reality is perceived reality. In choosing between these two basic strategic alternatives, Israel could opt for nuclear deterrence based upon assured destruction. Here, it would run an enlarged risk of 'losing' any nuclear war that might still arise. This is because countervalue-targeted nuclear weapons, by definition, would not destroy military targets. If, on the other hand, Israel were to opt for nuclear deterrence based upon counterforce capabilities, its Arab/Islamic enemies could feel especially threatened, a condition that could actually heighten the prospect of a nuclear exchange.

Israel's decisions on countervalue versus counterforce doctrines should depend, in part, on prior investigations of: (1) enemy country inclinations to strike first; and (2) enemy country inclinations to strike all-at-once or in stages. Should Israeli strategic planners assume that certain enemy countries that are in process of 'going nuclear' are apt to strike first and to strike in an unlimited fashion (that is, to fire all of their nuclear weapons right away), Israeli counterforce-targeted warheads - used in retaliation - would likely hit only empty silos/launchers. In such circumstances, Israel's only rational application of counterforce doctrine could be to strike first itself. If, for whatever reason, Israel were to reject preemption options, there would be no reason to opt for a counterforce strategy. Rather, from the standpoint of persuasive intrawar deterrence, a countervalue strategy could prove substantially more appropriate.

Should Israeli planners assume that the enemy countries 'going nuclear' are apt to strike first and to strike in a limited fashion - holding some significant measure of nuclear firepower in reserve for follow-on strikes - Israeli counterforce-targeted warheads could have damage-limiting benefits. Here, counterforce operations could serve both an Israeli preemption, or, should Israel decide not to preempt, an Israeli retaliatory strike. Moreover, should an Israeli first-strike be intentionally limited, perhaps because it would be coupled with an assurance of no further destruction in exchange for an end to hostilities, such operations could serve an Israeli counter-retaliatory strike. This is because Israel's attempt at intrawar deterrence could fail, occasioning the need for follow-on strikes to produce badly needed damage-limitation. Israeli preparations for nuclear warfighting should not be understood as a distinct alternative to preparations for nuclear deterrence. Instead, such preparations could be essential components of Israeli nuclear deterrence. A vital connection may exist between likely prowess/success in war and the quality of pre-war nuclear deterrence. Looking back, it is plain that regional nuclear war is a distinct possibility for Israel, and that adequate preparations need to be made now to prevent such a war. These preparations will require, immediately, a clear awareness of how a nuclear war might start in the Middle East, and an informed identification of the best strategic doctrine(s) currently available to Israel. This is not a pleasant subject, but it must not be avoided.



--------------------------------------------------------------------------------



Louis Rene Beres (Ph.D., Princeton, 1971), Professor, Department of Political Science, Purdue University, lectures and publishes widely on Israeli strategic matters. His work is well-known to Israel's military and academic communities. He is also the academic adviser at the Freeman Center for Strategic Studies, a Houston-based research facility and political action group.

reply by
Seth Sims: Carol, a must read
4/20/2002 (8:57)
 reply top
Informed Thoughts And Suggestions On Israel's Survival
13 June 2001


Those who place hope in outside protection for Israel, primarily from the U.S., assume - more or less - a continuation of traditional international relations. Yet, it is altogether likely that we live in an era of total fragmentation and disunity, a worldwide anarchy that will give new meaning to 'Westphalian' international relations and reinforce, rather than reduce, the self-help imperative. Hence, if this presumption of further global disintegration is to be taken seriously by Israeli planners, they will have to accept, however reluctantly, the obligation to face overriding dangers alone. One is reminded here of THE SECOND COMING, the poem by the great Irish poet William Butler Yeats:
Turning and turning in the widening gyre
The falcon cannot hear the falconer;
Things fall apart; the centre cannot hold;
Mere anarchy is loosed upon the world,
The blood-dimmed tide is loosed, and everywhere
The ceremony of innocence is drowned;
The best lack all conviction, while the worst
Are full of passionate intensity.
All world politics, and all global strategy, move in the midst of death. To truly understand calculations of war, deterrence and defense, Israeli planners need to understand (1) enemy orientations to death, both individual and collective; and (2) Israeli orientations to death, both individual and collective.

Heinrich von Treitschke, in his published lectures on POLITICS, cites approvingly to Fichte: 'Individual man sees in his country the realization of his earthly immortality.' Such 'seeing' among Israel's current enemies is a source of particular, even existential, danger. The danger is exacerbated by lack of symmetry with 'individual man' in Israel, who most assuredly sees such 'realization' much less in his own country.

There is great danger for Israel in presuming too much Reason in enemy decision-making and world affairs. Today the use of violence within and between states is often self-propelled and self-rewarding, effectively supplanting Clausewsitz with De Sade. The argument has been made most convincingly by Milan Kundera, in his book THE ART OF THE NOVEL. Describing a sheer force of violence that wills to assert itself as force, he talks about this force as 'naked, as naked as in Kafka's novels....The aggressivity of force is thoroughly disinterested; unmotivated; it wills only its own will; it is pure irrationality.' If Kundera is correct, what is Israel to do about its enemies? What shall it assume about enemy decision- making processes? Should not Israeli planners throw out the handbooks of political scientists and strategic theorists in favor of Kafka and Kundera? And what, exactly, can they learn from the 'fiction' writers?

The great Romanian (French) playwright, Eugene Ionesco, died in April 1994. In his only novel, THE HERMIT, Ionesco claims: 'People kill and are killed in order to prove to themselves that life exists.' Although a broad philosophical reflection, rather than an immediately useful strategic maxim, it says much about intentions of Israel's enemies and, by extension, about Israel's prospective responses.

To understand and predict global responses to Israeli actions in world affairs, Israeli planners must never forget that their country is always the Jew in macrocosm. For the world, macrocosm and microcosm are indistinguishable and indissoluble. Hence, for Israeli planners to expect global responses to Israeli actions to be detached from millenia of prejudicial hatreds is foolish in the extreme. Israel is not just another state, one among many others. It is unique, sui generis, not in the sense that it is believed to warrant greater justice (a post-Holocaust conclusion one might expect in a world dominated by Reason) but in the sense that it allegedly deserves less, always less, than every other state. Israel and justice cannot be uttered in the same breath for the same reason that Jews and justice cannot be uttered in the same breath. Israel, the Jew in macrocosm, will always be despised, will always be kept distanced from justice. Israeli decision-makers must always plan accordingly.

With further regard to Israel and considerations of justice (again, a paradoxical conjunction of terms), it must be recalled that histories of victimization have never conferred survival upon a people or a state, least of all upon the Jewish People. Such recollection stands in marked contrast to the oft-stated wish that terrible suffering, as in the matter of the Holocaust, cannot possibly be in vain. Eugene Ionesco, for example, offers the following passage from Andre Gide's JOURNAL, dated January 29, 1932: 'The idea that so much suffering can be in vain is intolerable to me, it kept me awake all night....' As a 'good Westerner,' continues Ionesco, 'Andre Gide couldn't help but think that suffering was the price of happiness, that suffering has to be rewarded.' Yet, Israeli planners must not forget that the world hardly ever pities those who suffer; all the more those who suffer greatly. Often, suffering creates scorn. So it is today with Jewish suffering, the Holocaust and the State of Israel.

Israeli planners are not philosophers. But they should recall Horace's recipe: 'Si vis me flere dolendum est primum ipsi tibi' - if you want me to weep, you must first grieve yourself. Before Israel can expect concern from the world, for its past and for its future, its own population must 'first grieve' itself; must care, deeply and profoundly and publicly, for its own history and its own essential continuity; for surviving at all costs. Paradoxically, current government policies of sequential concessions and territorial 'compromise' display the very opposite of such needed 'grief,' suggesting an unwarranted degree of 'understanding' and inflated national self-confidence. Further, post-Zionist private sentiments, now widespread throughout Israel, that collective meaning for the post-Holocaust Jewish State is more discoverable in Los Angeles than in enduring Jewish values, also reject essential forms of 'grief.'

Regarding judgments of rationality and deterrence, Israeli planners must never fail to put themselves into the shoes of enemy decision-makers. What will impact these decision-makers, and therefore Israel's safety, will not be Israeli perceptions or even some 'objectively correct' set of facts, but only what they perceive as real. Hence, what may well appear prudent and rational in Tel-Aviv could be taken as cowardly and irrational in Teheran or Damascus. I have in mind, for example, differential views on Israel's decision not to retaliate for 39 Iraqi Scud missile attacks during the 1991 Gulf War. What will be the long-term effects of this decision on Israel's overall deterrence posture? This is an important question, one that needs to be asked again and again and again.

Israeli planners focus, of course, on enemy capabilities and intentions. But do they focus on each variable as separate and discrete, or rather as interdependent and synergistic? As one can affect the other, only the latter orientation is correct and productive.

Israel is unable to ensure its security, even its survival, through reliance on ballistic missile defense and U.S. guarantees. Rather, barring radical transformation of enemy regimes, Jerusalem will have no existential choice but to preemptively destroy unconventional weapons and supporting infrastructures in a timely manner. Although the currently fashionable idea of a 'multilayered defense' has its attractions (above all, it puts off the preemption imperative by highlighting far more palatable tactical options), in the end it will mean little. It follows that Israeli planners should look closely and immediately at the following threat dimensions: (1) expected probability of enemy first-strikes over time; (2) expected disutility of enemy first-strikes over time (itself dependent, inter alia, on nature of enemy weaponry, projected enemy targeting doctrines, and multiplication/dispersion/hardening of Israeli unconventional forces); (3) expected collaborative prospects between enemy states (and possibly between enemy state and non-state actors); (4) expected schedules of enemy unconventional weapons deployments; (5) expected efficiency of enemy active defenses over time; (6) expected efficiency of Israeli active defenses over time; (7) expected efficiency of Israeli hard-target counterforce operations over time; and (8) expected world community reactions to Israeli preemptions. It goes without saying that Israel's commitment to the 'Peace Process' has greatly impaired its essential preemption option, and that such commitment is even more injurious to Israeli survival than is commonly understood.

The dangers to Israel of a Palestinian state must be understood within the general context of concern for Israeli nuclear strategy and regional nuclear war. Should the 'Peace Process' produce a state of Palestine, which is now certain, Israel's substantial loss of strategic depth will be recognized by enemy states, especially by Iran, Iraq, Egypt and Syria, as a significant liability for Jerusalem. Such recognition, in turn, will heat up enemy state intentions against Israel, occasioning an accelerated search for capabilities and, consequently, a heightened risk of war initiated from Teheran or Baghdad or Cairo or Damascus. Israeli planners, of course, might forsee such enemy calculations and seek to compensate for the loss of territories in a number of different ways. For example, Jerusalem could decide to take its bomb out of the 'basement' (as a deterrence-enhancing measure) and/or it could accept a heightened willingness to launch preemptive strikes against enemy hard targets. Made aware of such Israeli intentions, intentions that would accrue from Israel's new vulnerabilities, enemy states could respond in a more or less parallel fashion, preparing more openly for nuclearization and/or for first-strike attacks against the Jewish State.

The phrase, 'Death to Israel,' like the phrase 'Death to the Jews,' is a phrase that is always uttered in chorus. A hater of Israel, like a hater of individual Jews, is always attached to a crowd or to a mob. In such hatreds, one cannot be alone. It is this communal tradition of hatred, more than anything else, that draws adherents - both among the nations and among peoples within nations. There is little point in seeking to transform this tradition, which is deeply embedded in a generically human desperation to belong. Instead, those who are responsible for Israeli safety and security from enemy attacks should now focus exclusively on what can be changed.

Israeli planners must protect Israel's nuclear forces by some combination of multiplication/dispersion/hardening. Enemy planners, observing such measures, might perceive preparations for an Israeli first-strike. Such erroneous perceptions are all the more likely should Israel simultaneously seek further force protection via appropriate forms of active and passive defenses. Ironically, in seeking to stabilize deterrence by signaling enemy states that its own nuclear forces are secure from enemy first strikes - i.e., that these are exclusively second-strike forces with 'assured destruction' capability - Jerusalem could create the impression that it is preparing to strike first. Here, Israel's attempts to convince enemy states that it is not preparing for preemption could backfire, generating new incentives to these enemy states to 'preempt' themselves. The alternative, for Israel, would be to deliberately disguise efforts at nuclear force protection from enemy states, but such subterfuge would also carry considerable risk. After all, should Israel's enemies calculate that Jerusalem's nuclear forces are insufficiently protected from first- strike attacks, they would want to exploit current but potentially transient Israeli weakness. Moreover, because insufficient force protection by Jerusalem could encourage Israeli first-strikes, Israel's enemies would have compelling reasons to launch prompt 'preemptive' attacks.

Regarding the legal right to preemption, Israel's planners may wish to recall the authoritative jurisprudential argument of Hugo Grotius in his COMMENTARY ON THE LAW OF PRIZE AND BOOTY: 'Now, as Cicero explains, this (justification for anticipatory self-defense) exists whenever he who chooses to wait (for formal declarations of war) will be obliged to pay an unjust penalty before he can exact a just penalty; and, in a general sense, it exists whenever matters do not admit of delay. Thus it is obvious that a just war can be waged in return, without recourse to judicial procedure, against an opponent who has begun an unjust war; nor will any declaration of that just war be required....For, as Aelian says, citing Plato as his authority, any war undertaken for the necessary repulsion of injury, is proclaimed not by a crier nor by a herald but by the voice of Nature herself.'

Israel's military planners must consider important complex relationships between C3I vulnerability and predelegations of launch authority. To reduce the risks of 'decapitation,' an objective as essential to Israeli nuclear deterrence as protection of the weapons themselves, Jerusalem might consider increasing the number of authoritative decision-makers who would have the right to launch under certain carefully-defined residual contingencies. But because the deterrence value of such an increase would require that prospective enemies learn (however indirectly and incompletely) that Israel had taken these decapitation-avoidance predelegations (after all, without such learning, enemies would be more apt to calculate that first-strike attacks are cost-effective), those enemies might feel increasingly compelled to 'preempt.' These premption incentives would derive from new enemy state fears of a fully intentional Israeli first-strike and/or new fears of accidental, unauthorized or unintentional nuclear strikes from Israel. Aware of these probable enemy reactions to its predelegations of launch authority, predelegations which might or might not be complemented by launch-on-warning measures, Israel, reciprocally, could feel compelled to actually strike first, a preemption of preemptive attack that may or may not prove to be net gainful and that may or may not have been avoided by antecedent resistance to predelegations of launch authority. Significantly, this entire scenario could be 'played' in the other direction. Here, Iran or an Arab state enemy seeking to reduce its decapitation risks would implement predelegations of launch authority, thereby encouraging Israeli preemptions and, as a consequence, Iranian and/or Arab state 'preemptions of Israeli preemption.' If all of this sounds dreadfully complicated, it is because this is a dreadfully complicated business. Those who do not feel comfortable with dreadful complications should not be in the strategic planning business. Israel does not need IDF simplifiers. It does not need more 'experts.' It needs broadly educated planners who are willing to fashion an indispensable strategic dialectic, a nuanced genre that goes well beyond the purely journalistic/reportorial 'expertise' of current academic strategists.

The destructiveness of nuclear weapons continues to pose conceptual problems for Israeli planners (military and civilian) and academic strategists. Fearful of association with such terrible weapons, these planners and strategists too often dance around the most urgent questions. As a result, nuclear war involving Israel may become more likely and security benefits that might have been identified in advance may be lost forever.

Israel's planners should be reminded of M. Unamuno's instructive remark about Hegel: 'Hegel made famous his aphorism that all the rational is real and all the real rational; but there are many of us who, unconvinced by Hegel, continue to believe that the real, the really real, is irrational, that reason builds upon irrationalities.' For Israel, faced with the prospect of unconventional aggression from enemy states, it would be prudent to 'build upon irrationalities,' i.e., upon the expected irrationalities of an increasingly formidable enemy.

In considering the operation of nuclear deterrence and associated matters of nuclear strategy, including preremption, Israeli planners may recall that such operation impacts and determines the adequacy of pertinent international law. For example, the adequacy of international law in preventing nuclear war in the Middle East will depend not only upon certain treaties (e.g., the Nonproliferation Treaty), customs and general principles of jurisprudence, but also upon the success or failure of particular country strategies in the region. Hence, if Israel's strategy should reduce the threat of nuclear war, either because of successful forms of deterrence or because of essential nonnuclear preemptive strikes, such strategy would have to be considered an essential component of international law.

Even if it could be assumed, by Israeli planners, that enemy state leaders will always be rational, a problematic assumption, to be sure, this would say nothing about the accuracy of information used in making rational calculations. Rationality, we must recall, refers only to the intention of maximizing specified values or preferences. It says nothing at all about whether the information used is correct or incorrect. Hence, rational enemy state leaders may make errors in calculation that lead to war against Israel.

Where Israel should face enemy states bent upon a war of extermination (and where have they faced a different enemy), the following jurisprudential understanding should not be lost: War and genocide need not be mutually exclusive. War might well be the means whereby genocide is undertaken. This should be as obvious today as it was during and after the Holocaust. According to Articles II and III of the Genocide Convention, which entered into force on January 12, 1951, genocide includes any of several listed acts 'committed with intent to destroy, in whole or in part, a national, ethnical, racial or religious group as such....' It follows that where Israel is identified as the institutionalized expression of the Jewish People (an expression that includes national, ethnical, racial and religious components) acts of war intended to destroy the Jewish State could assuredly be genocidal. Here it should be remembered that international law is not a suicide pact; nowhere is it written that Israel must wait patiently for a second genocidal assault.

Like it or not, Israeli planners must consider the prospect of Israeli nuclear preemption against enemy hard targets. Ironically, this prospect could be heightened to the extent that Israel puts off non-nuclear preemptions against developing enemy nuclear assets. If it waits too long to exercise conventional preemption options, Israel could face a choice between (1) undertaking nuclear preemption and ensuring survival of the Third Temple Commonwealth; or (2) resisting nuclear preemption and risking destruction of the Third Temple Commonwealth. Israeli planners could accept the rationality of Option 1 where: (a) Israel's state enemy had acquired and deployed nuclear and/or other unconventional weapons judged capable of destroying the Third Temple Commonwealth; (b) Israel's state enemies had made clear that their intentions paralleled their capabilities; (c) Israel's state enemies were believed ready by Israeli decsion-makers to begin a 'countdown to launch;' and (d) Jerusalem believed that Israeli non- nuclear preemptions could not achieve the needed minimum level of damage- limitation, i.e., levels consistent with preservation of the State.

I am aware that the juxtaposition of Israel and Jewish extermination inherent in references to 'destruction of the Third Temple Commonwealth' is so dreadful that it borders on sacrilege. Yet, it is a juxtaposition that should not be ignored or disregarded. Should Israeli planners fail to take it seriously, the concentration of millions of post-Holocaust Jews in an area smaller than a large county in California could prove a blessing to those among Israel's enemies who would refashion genocide as war. But if we do take seriously the connections between Zionist objectives and Jewish vulnerability in the Third Commonwealth, we will have taken the first critical steps toward ensuring Israeli security, toward making certain that Jewish liberation does not become Jewish misfortune.

Applied to Israel and the Middle East, the fashionable concepts of 'security regime' and 'confidence building measures' are sheer nonsense, the deleterious fabrications of academics dedicated to looking away from an uncomfortable reality. Exploiting Israeli frustration and fatigue, such concepts appear enormously tempting. They are, however, unforgivably dangerous, generating faith in a 'Peace Process' that points only to Israel's dismemberment and disappearance.

There is a marked tendency in Israel to imitate American strategic thinking. This is a serious mistake, as virtually all American academic strategists are paid not to think and, above all, not to depart from prudent (and therefore intellectually sterile) forms of prescription. To use the language of Jose Ortega y Gasset, whose REVOLT OF THE MASSES (1932) is one of the most important books of our century, today's Ph.D. 'expert' in Washington or Tel-Aviv is essentially a 'learned ignoramus, which is a very serious matter, as it implies that he is a person who is ignorant, not in the fashion of the ignorant man, but with all the petulance of one who is learned in his own special line.'

For Israel, the future cannot be separated from the past. They are indissolubly interconnected. To prepare for the future, Israel's leaders must look closely at the past, not only from 1948 onward, but for 5000 years. The point is more than the cliched imperative to learn the 'lessons of history.' It is to understand that Jewish history is altogether sui generis, that Israel's history is an integral part of this Jewish history, and that an erroneous 'cosmopolitanism' (i.e., 'Jews are just another people in the worldwide community of humankind') could be a particularly serious mistake.

Regarding the methods of Israeli strategic analysis, it is essential that they be based upon an appropriate dialectic. Hence, analysts must approach their problem as an interrelated series of thoughts, where each thought or idea about, for example, enemy capabilities/intentions presents a complication that moves inquiry onward to the next thought or idea. Contained in this strategic dialectic is an obligation to continue thinking, an obligation that can never be fulfilled entirely (because of what the philosophers call the 'infinite regress problem'), but that must still be attempted as fully and as competently as possible. Without such a dialectic, those who work on Israeli security matters will continue to focus only upon discrete moments in time, on static phenomena (e.g., numbers of weapons; types of weapons; leadership personalities, etc), rather than upon appropriately dynamic and generic interactions (synergies).

The term 'dialectic' originates from the Greek expression for the art of conversation. Today, a common meaning is that dialectic is a method of seeking truth via correct reasoning. From the standpoint of our concerns, the following operations may be identified as essential but non-exclusive components of a strategic dialectic: (1) A method of refutation by examining logical consequences; (2) A method of division or repeated logical analysis of genera into species; (3) Logical reasoning using premises that are probable or generally accepted; (4) Formal logic; and (5) The logical development of thought through thesis and antithesis to a synthesis of these opposites.

Dialectic likely originated in the 5th century B.C.E., as Zeno, author of the famous PARADOXES, was recognized by Aristotle as its inventor. In the middle dialogues of Plato, dialectic emerges as the supreme form of philosophical/analytic method. In one of these dialogues, Plato describes the dialectician as someone who knows how to ask and to answer questions. This is what should now be transposed to the study of Israeli security matters. We need, in these all-important matters, to know how to ask and to answer questions. This knowledge must precede compilations of facts, figures, and power 'balances.'

The dialectician needs to recognize the advantages of private as opposed to collective thought. Here we are reminded of Aristotle's view: 'Deception occurs to a greater extent when we are investigating with others than by ourselves, for an investigation with someone else is carried on quite as much by means of the thing itself.' Understood in terms of Israeli strategic analysis, this suggests some serious limitations to 'teamwork,' 'group projects,' 'centers for strategic studies,' 'expert collaboration,' etc. It is not that these forms of investigation are inappropriate per se, but that they must be tempered by sober private thinking.

The advantages of a new Israeli strategic dialectic will depend, in part, upon the coherence of the overall academic enterprise. Israel does not face a random set of discrete and wholly separate military threats. Rather, there is a general threat environment within which discrete threat components fit. The task for Israeli academic strategists is not to figure out in advance each and every specific threat component (this is a task of certain government intelligence analysts), but to identify a strategy which will accomodate the understanding of a broad variety of possible threats. This means, inter alia, an obligation to fashion a strategic 'master plan,' a body of generalized and interrelated propositions from which specific policy options can be derived. Such a plan would not contain all or even most of the 'answers,' but it would offer a comprehensive and informed framework within which all of the important questions might be addressed. Significantly, such a plan would never be 'completed.' It would serve those who oversee Israel's security needs continually, incrementally and directly, as an ongoing and expanding set of purposeful guidelines.

'In the areas with which we are concerned,' wrote Walter Benjamin, 'insight only occurs as a lightning bolt. The text is the thunder-peal rolling long behind.' For us, such an 'area' is Israeli strategic studies. It is an area that will be ill-served by standard thinking and texts. It is an area that can only be served productively by flashes of understanding that defy (and quite probably contradict) mainstream assessments and analyses.

The current and ongoing disintegration of the world is creation in reverse. For Israel, the Jewish State, there are therefore special lessons to be learned from this disintegration. The geometry of chaos, in a strange and paradoxical symmetry, reveals both sense and form. How shall they be discovered? This is an important question, one that goes far beyond the usual sorts of ON WAR and TRANSFORMATION OF WAR queries. It must not be ignored.

Israel, it seems, can contemplate the end of the Third Temple Commonwealth every day, and yet persevere quite calmly in its most routine and mundane affairs. This should not be the case if Israel could begin to contemplate the moment of its collective disappearance. It follows that Israel must begin immediately to replace reassuringly abstract conceptualizations of End Times with unbearably concrete imaginings of catastrophe. Only then could the leaders of Israel take the steps needed to survive into the Third Millennium.

There exists, among Israel's enemies, a voluptuousness all their own; the voluptuousness of conflict against the Jewish State as such. It is in Israel's strategic interest not to lose sight of this voluptuousness. Israel's enemies, in good part, do not read Clausewitz. They are, in good measure, animated by more primal needs and expectations.

E.M. Cioran, the most dazzling and devastating French philosophical voice since Paul Valery (and an original thinker in the tradition of Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Wittgenstein) writes of the Jews as a 'People of Solitaries,' a People, for all of its recognized lucidity, that 'readily sacrifices to illusion: it hopes, it always hopes too much....With so many enemies, any other people, in its place, would have laid down its arms; but this nation, unsuited to the complacencies of despair, bypassing its age-old fatigue and the conclusions imposed by its fate, lives in the delirium of expectation, determined not to learn a lesson from its humiliations....' How true, how especially true is this observation of a 'nation' for the State of the Jews, the State of Israel.

When Pericles delivered his Funeral Oration and other speeches, with their praise of Athenian civilization, his perspective was largely military. Recorded by Thucydides, an historian whose main interest was to study the growth and use of power for military objectives, the speeches of Pericles express confidence in ultimate victory for Athens, but they also express grave concern for self-imposed setbacks along the way: 'What I fear more than the strategies of our enemies is our own mistakes.' Although Pericles exaggerated the separateness of enemy strategies and Athenian mistakes (they were, of course, interrelated and even synergistic), there is an important lesson here for Israel. In observing enemy preparations for war, do not forget that the effectiveness of these preparations will always depend upon Israel's particular responses.

Under contemporary international law, the right of self-defense is not confined to post-attack circumstances. Rather, it extends, under carefully defined conditions, to preemptive or 'anticipatory' strikes. In this connection, Israel's leaders and planners should recall Pufendorf's authoritative argument in his ON THE DUTY OF MAN AND CITIZEN ACCORDING TO NATURAL LAW: '...where it is quite clear that the other is already planning an attack upon me, even though he has not yet fully revealed his intentions, it will be permitted at once to begin forcible self-defense, and to anticipate him who is preparing mischief, provided there be no hope that, when admonished in a friendly spirit, he may put off his hostile temper, or if such admonition be likely to injure our cause. Hence, he is to be regarded as the aggressor, who first conceived the wish to injure, and prepared himself to carry it out. But the excuse of self-defense will be his, who by quickness shall overpower his slower assailant. And for defense, it is not required that one receive the first blow, or merely avoid and parry those aimed at him.'

A passage in the ODYSSEY speaks of two gates, one of horn and one of ivory. Through the ivory gate false dreams pass to humankind, and through the gate of horn go only the true and prophetic dreams. At this moment in its always precarious history, Israel is sorely tempted by the ivory gate, choosing to base preservation of the Third Temple Commonwealth upon fanciful visions of a 'Peace Process,' 'confidence building measures' and 'security communities.' Israel would be far better off, however, to pass instead through the gate of horn, preparing to use military force selectively and preemptively in order to endure. This decision will likely occasion greater pain and uncertainty in the short run, but it would base preservation of the Third Temple Commonwealth upon altogether sober assessments of REALPOLITIK and would affirm, rather than reject, the essential obligations of international law.

According to al-Da'wa (THE MISSION), an Islamic publication, the status of Israel is identical to the status of the individual Jew. What is this status? 'The race (sic) is corrupt at the root, full of duplicity, and the Muslims have everything to lose in seeking to deal with them; they must be exterminated.' Historically, the Islamic world's orientation to extermination of the Jews has not been limited to phrasemaking. Even before Israel came into existence in May 1948, on November 28, 1941, the Grand Mufti of Jerusalem, Haj Amin, met in Berlin with Adolph Hitler. The declared subject of their meeting was nothing less than 'the final solution of the Jewish Question.' This meeting, which followed Haj Amin's active organization of Muslim SS troops in Bosnia, included the Mufti's promise to aid German victory in the war. Later, after Israel's trial and punishment of Adolph Eichmann in 1961, Iranian and Arab newspapers described the mass murderer of Jews as a 'martyr,' congratulating him posthumously for having 'conferred a real blessing on humanity' by liquidating six million 'subhumans.'

Regarding American orientations to genocide in the Middle East, Israel would do well to recall Reagan and Bush administration indifference to extermination of the Kurds. Iraqi documents seized during the Kurdish uprising in March and April 1991 detail mass slayings of civilians, including videotapes of executions, beatings and torture. United States authorities, for years, encouraged Kurdish revolt, and then betrayed this unfortunate people to genocidal destruction. During the late 1980s, the U.S. stood by silently as Saddam Hussein's regime systematically demolished Kurdish villages and towns, and forcibly transferred a half million or more Kurds into specially-created concentration camps. In March of 1991, after encouraging the Iraqi Kurds to rise up against the Baghdad regime, the Bush administration did nothing to prevent new crushing genocidal blows against the Kurds by the Iraqi army.

From the standpoint of international law, we must distinguish preemptive attacks from preventive ones. Preemption represents a strategy of striking an enemy first, in the expectation that the only alternative is to be struck first oneself. A preemptive attack is launched by a state that believes enemy forces are about to attack. A preventive attack, however, is launched not out of concern for imminent hostilities, but for fear of a longer-term deterioration in the pertinent military balance. Hence, in a preemptive attack, the length of time by which the enemy's action is anticipated is very short, while in a preventive strike the interval is considerably longer. A problem for Israel, in this regard, is not only the practical difficulty in determining imminence, but also the fact that delaying a defensive strike until imminence is plausible could be fatal.

In the strict jurisprudential sense, because a state of war exists between Israel and Iran (at Iran's particular insistence), the Jewish State does not need to meet the requirements of anticipatory self-defense. Rather, as there can be no authentic preemption in an ongoing belligerency, an Israeli 'first strike' against Iran would need only to fulfill the expectations of the laws of war, i.e., the rules of discrimination, proportionality and military necessity. A legal state of war can exist between two states irrespective of the presence or absence of ongoing hostilities between national armed forces. The principle affirming that the existence of a legal state of war depends upon the intentions of one or more of the states involved, and not on 'objective' phenomena, is known variously as the 'state of war doctrine;' 'de jure war;' 'war in the legal sense' and 'war in the sense of international law.'

Confronting what he calls 'our century of fear,' Albert Camus would have us all be 'neither victims nor executioners,' living not in a world in which killing has disappeared ('we are not so crazy as that!'), but one wherein killing has become illegitimate. This is a fine expectation, to be sure, yet unless it is fashioned with a promising view toward effective nonlethal measures of preserving order and justice, the result will certainly be an enlargement of pain and terror. Deprived of the capacity to act as lawful executioners, states facing aggression would be forced by Camus' reasoning to become victims. Why is Camus so sorely mistaken? Where, exactly, has he gone wrong? The answer, it would seem, lies in his presumption, however implicit, of a natural reciprocity among human beings and states in the matter of killing. More specifically, we are asked to believe that as greater numbers of people agree not to be executioners, still greater numbers will follow upon the same course. In time, the argument proceeds, the number of those who refuse to sanction killing will become so great that there will be fewer and fewer victims. The problem, of course, is that Camus' presumed reciprocity does not exist. The will to kill, as we have learned from so many for so long, is unimpressed by particular commitments to 'goodness.' It follows that executioners may have their rightful place in world politics, and that without them there would only be more victims.

In the realm of world politics, executioners sometimes function as assassins. Although such functioning is almost always an instance of wrongful execution, there are certain carefully circumscribed and residual cases where it may be rightful, permissible, and even distinctly law enforcing. Understood in terms of Israel's security needs, this points to the option of assassination as a form of anticipatory self-defense. In determining whether or not a particular instance of assassination would qualify as such a form under international law, the act: (1) must not be designed to achieve a prohibited objective, but only to forestall destruction of Israel's land and people; and (2) must meet the legal test known to international lawyers as the Caroline - i.e., the danger that gives rise to the preemptive attack by Israel must be judged 'instant, overwhelming, leaving no choice of means and no moment for deliberation.' Thus, if the assassination is undertaken only to destroy the potential threat of the enemy (as a preventive action), it would not qualify as permissible under international law. If, however, the assassination were undertaken in anticipation of immediate enemy aggression (as a preemptive action), it could qualify as an instance of anticipatory self-defense.

There are several problems here. First, in the real world, judgments concerning the immediacy of anticipated aggression are exceedingly difficult to make. Second, even where such judgments are ventured, it can never be altogether clear whether the degree of immediacy is sufficient to invoke preemption rather than prevention. Third, in meeting the aforestated legal requirements of defensive intent (#1 above), Israel may have to act preventively rather than preemptively (because waiting to allow a threat to become more immediate could have decisively negative strategic/tactical consequences. And fourth, the actual state-preserving benefits that might accrue to Israel from assassination of enemy leaders are apt to be contingent upon not waiting until the danger posed is 'instant, overwhelming, leaving no choice of means and no moment for deliberation.' Assessments of the lawfulness of assassination as anticipatory self-defense must also include comparisons with alternative forms of preemption. If, for example, the perceived alternative to assassination is large-scale uses of force taking the form of defensive military strikes, a utilitarian or 'balance of harms' criterion could surely favor assassination. Such a choice may well have to be made sometime soon in Jerusalem, especially as the territories are transformed into a Palestinian state. Here, deprived of strategic depth, Israel could calculate that it had only three real options: (1) do nothing, rely entirely on deterrence, and hope that enemy states remain dissuaded from striking first; (2) strike preemptively with military force against selected hard targets in enemy states, and hope that substantial reprisals are prevented by persuasive intra-war deterrence, i.e., by compelling Israeli threats of unacceptably damaging counter-retaliation; or (3) strike preemptively by assassination, and hope that this will reduce the overall threat to Israel without escalating into full-fledged military encounters. Although impossible to determine in the abstract, Option 3 might well prove to be the most cost-effective one available to Israel in certain circumstances.

Jurisprudentially, of course, it would be reasonable to examine assassination as a possible form of ordinary self-defense, i.e., as a forceful measure of self-help short of war that is undertaken after an armed attack occurs. Tactically, however, there are at least two serious problems with such an examination. First, in view of the ongoing proliferation of extraordinarily destructive weapons technologies among Israel's enemies in the Middle East, waiting to resort to ordinary self- defense could be very dangerous, if not altogether fatal. Second, assassination, while it may prove helpful in preventing an attack upon Israel in the first place, is far less likely to be useful in mitigating further harm once an attack has already been launched.

Martin Van Creveld writes, in THE TRANSFORMATION OF WAR, that as the lines between political violence and criminal violence become blurred, assassination of enemy leaders will become more fashionable: 'Over the last three centuries or so, attempts to assassinate or otherwise incapacitate leaders were not regarded as part of the game of war. In the future, there will be a tendency to regard such leaders as criminals who richly deserve the worst fate that can be inflicted upon them.' From the standpoint of international law, a case in point is Saddam Hussein. Based upon the peremptory principle of law known as Nullum crimen sine poena, 'No crime without a punishment,' leaving Saddam in power, unpunished, was altogether unjust. At Nuremberg, the words used by the Court, 'So far from it being unjust to punish him, it would be unjust if his wrong were allowed to go unpunished,' represented an authoritative reaffirmation of this principle. The earliest statement of Nullum crimen sine poena can be found in the Code of Hammurabi (c. 1728 - 1686 BCE); the Laws of Eshnunna (c. 2000 BCE); the even-earlier code of Ur-Nammu (c. 2100 BCE), and, most significantly for Israel, the Lex Talionis or law of exact retaliation, presented in three separate passages of the Torah. For ancient Hebrews, when a crime involved the shedding of blood, not only punishment - but punishment involving a reciprocal bloodletting - was required. Shedding of blood is an abomination that must be expiated, 'for blood pollutes the land, and no expiation can be made for the land, for the blood that is shed in it, except by the blood of him who shed it.' (NUM. 35:33)

Israel, the Jew in macrocosm, has become uncomfortable with the use of power, especially that form of power based upon armed force. In a world of growing international anarchy, this development represents a serious liability. Left unchecked, it could become fatal.

The obligation to use armed force in a world of international anarchy forms the central argument of Realpolitik from the Melian Dialogues of Thucydides and Cicero to Machiavelli, Locke, Spykman and Kissinger. 'For what can be done against force without force?', asks Cicero in one of his Letters. Later, in our own century, Nicholas Spykman replies: 'In a world of international anarchy, foreign policy must aim above all at the improvement or at least the preservation of the relative power position of the state.' Such arguments are assuredly not incorrect, but it is likely that, today, they have become markedly trivial. The anarchy we confront in world politics today is vastly different from its predecessors; it is more far- reaching, extending not only between states but within them. It is almost primordial, the anarchy of William Golding's Lord of the Flies; it is sui generis. What does this suggest about Israel's particular security options? How should Israel's leadership plan in the face of this new kind of anarchy? How will Israel be affected by anarchy amidst its enemies? And how will it be affected by anarchy amongst its 'friends?'

Van Creveld's TRANSFORMATION OF WAR is right on the mark in underscoring humankind's seemingly irrational delight in the use of armed force, an authentic joy in the spirit of war. This observation is an indispensable corrective to the popular notion that everyone is always agreed upon the undesirability and unattractiveness of war, a notion with origins in the poetry of the Classical Age, the poetry of Pindar: 'Sweet is war to him who knows it not, but to those who have made trial of it, it is a thing of fear.' Similar expressions are found in the less-than-exultant tone of the herald's tale of victory in the AGAMEMNON; the harsh words of Euripides for that same victory in the TROADES; the poignant words of Pericles regarding those who had perished in Samos: 'It was as if the spring had been taken from the year.' Yet, even before Van Creveld, Michael Howard pointed out: 'In Western Europe until the first part of the seventeenth century, warfare was a way of life for considerable sections of society, its termination was for them a catastrophe, and its prolongation, official or unofficial, was the legitimate objective of every man of spirit.' In the eighteenth century, war was accepted by many as an essential element of social life, one needed to combat what the philosopher Kant called 'mere commercial spirit, and with it a debasing self-interest.'

There is a dramatic affinity between war and the personal fear of death. Although it is unlikely that Israeli planners will read Lucretius's great poem, ON THE NATURE OF THINGS, the 'message' of the Epicurean text has serious implications for Israeli security. What the young Virgil, citing Lucretius, called fear of 'the doom against which no prayer avails' leads humankind to destroy life. Because the individual fails to understand the balance between destructive and creative forces, he/she is anxious about personal dissolution. This individual, to use the mythical terms set forth by Lucretius himself, will be on the side of Mars rather than Venus, reaching out to the rest of the world aggressively rather than compassionately. Persons, and therefore collectivites of persons known as States, have an incorrect attitude toward death that turns them to the terrible pleasures of violence. The very last scene of Lucretius's poem is a bloody battle that would not have occurred if individuals had understood death. Humankind surrenders to death and dismemberment precisely because it fears death and dismemberment. How characteristic and insightful, indeed prophetic, are these ancient observations regarding current Islamic thought about war, terrorism and 'infidels.' Israel should take note!

'Men as a rule willingly believe what they want to believe!' So says Caesar in Chapter 18 of the GALLIC WAR. For Israel, the impact of Caesar's insight became evident on October 6, 1973, with the start of the Yom Kippur War. Until then, the country had been committed to something known generally as 'the concept,' the kontzeptziya, the contrived idea that the Arabs were unwilling and incapable of renewing hostilities against the Jewish State. Aman's overall assessment of enemy designs, lasting until October 5, 1973, was that war was 'highly improbable' or 'improbable.' It was this fundamentally incorrect assumption that created a monumental intelligence blunder - the 'mehdal' in post-war Hebrew parlance. This is a blunder that could be repeated at far greater cost in the future. At the moment, the principal source of such a prospective blunder is the sentiment that sustains the 'Middle East Peace Process.'

The Oslo Agreements are null and void according to international law. All states are obligated by international law to seek out and prosecute the perpetrators of crimes of war, crimes against peace and crimes against humanity. The same obligation extends to crimes of terrorism. Derived from the peremptory norm of Nullum crimen sine poena! ('No Crime Without a Punishment!'), this obligation was violated flagrantly by Israel's 'peace' agreements with a terrorist organization. Indeed, recognizing that, according to Article 53 of the VIENNA CONVENTION ON THE LAW OF TREATIES, any agreement '...is void, if at the time of its conclusion, it conflicts with a peremptory norm of general international law,' the Oslo agreements, witnessed officially by representatives of the United States, should be disregarded. Conflicting with a peremptory or jus cogens norm, a norm that, according to Article 53 of the VIENNA CONVENTION is 'a norm accepted and recognized by the international community of states as a whole as a norm from which no derogation is permitted....,' the agreements confer no jurisprudential responsibilities of any kind.

The Palestine Liberation Organization was treated as a terrorist group in the Klinghoffer v. Palestine Liberation Organization (PLO) suit. Here, the court determined, inter alia, that the federal court had jurisdiction over the PLO. In this civil action, which alleged that 'the owner and charterer of the Achille Lauro, travel agencies and various other entities' failed to thwart the attack, jurisdiction was proffered on the basis of the Death on the High Seas Act (46 U.S.C. App. Secs. 761 - 767; 1982), diversity of citizenship and state law.

It is generally (but erroneously) believed that the peace treaty in force between Israel and Egypt constrains the latter from joining with other Arab states against the former. But a Minute to Article VI, paragraph 5, of the Israel-Egypt Peace Treaty provides that it is agreed by the parties that there is no assertion that the Peace Treaty prevails over other treaties or agreements, or that other treaties or agreements prevail over the Peace Treaty. (See Treaty of Peace, March 26, 1979, Egypt-Israel, Minute to Art. VI(5), 18 I.L.M., 362, 392.)

In all world politics, but especially in the Middle East, we are present at the gradual unveiling of a secret, but the nucleus of meaning, the essential truth of what is taking place, is what is not said. For the immediate future, the enemies of Israel will continue their preparations for chemical/biological/nuclear war. Altogether unaffected by parallel public commitments to 'peace process,' 'self-determination,' 'regional coexistence,' 'security regimes' and 'confidence building measures,' these preparations will proceed on their own track, culminating, if unobstructed, in new and substantially more portentous aggressions against Israel. It follows that Israel must not close its eyes to such enemy preparations or to the associated and synergistic dangers of a Palestinian state, one- sided denuclearization and one-sided peace settlements.

In the aftermath of the 1991 Gulf War, Israel - intrawar threats notwithstanding - decided not to respond with any retaliatory strikes to Iraq's 39 missile attacks. If Israel had decided to respond, presumably against Baghdad's pertinent military assets, this response could have been characterized by Jerusalem as any one of the following: (1) reprisal; (2) self-defense; or (3) anticipatory self-defense. Alternatively, Israel could have argued persuasively that: (4) a condition of war had existed between the Jewish State and Iraq since 1948 at Iraq's insistence, and that Israel's latest military strikes were not measures of self-help short of war (i.e., not instances of reprisal, self-defense or anticipatory self-defense) but rather just one more legitimate use of force in an ongoing conflict. In the final analysis, the lawfulness of Israel's counterstrike and the reasonableness of its characterization would have depended upon such facts as general moves toward peace underway in the region, amount of time elapsed between Iraq's aggression and Israel's response, and the level of continuing danger to Israel from the Baghdad regime. If Jerusalem had opted for number 4, supra, its military counterstrike would have been prima facie lawful so long as it had fulfilled the settled peremptory criteria of the laws of war - namely the expectations of discrimination, proportionality and military necessity.

Uncomfortable truths travel with great difficulty. Among these truths, one of the most distressing concerns the certain failure of the so-called nonproliferation regime. Highlighted by the Nonproliferation Treaty, which entered into force in 1970, this body of authoritative norms under international law is incapable of preventing the spread of nuclear weapons throughout the world. This means that reliance upon such a body of rules, however 'prudent' and well-intentioned, will likely hasten rather than inhibit the onset of nuclear war. What shall Israel do? When, at Arab insistence, Jerusalem is asked to join the NPT, as a non-nuclear member, how should it respond? If it should resist, the global community of 'civilized' nations would surely be aroused, declaring that, once again, a recalcitrant Israel had refused to follow the codified rules of international law. Should it accede to the Treaty, it would trade-off critical safety in exchange for favorable world public opinion. Of course, it could also do what Iraq and other Islamic states have always done, i.e., sign the Treaty but act as if no obligations whatever had been incurred - but such hypocrisy has never been Israel's style, nor should it be. It should also be recalled here that Israel has never obstructed diplomatic remedies to regional security. In addition to the agreements on Palestinian 'autonomy,' note the following: In January 1993, Israel became a charter signatory of the Chemical Weapons Convention (CWC), while Egypt, Syria and most other states in the area rejected the Treaty. Israel ratified the Limited Test Ban Treaty in 1964. It is a member of the International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA) and has safeguards agreements for several minor facilities. It has consistently supported the concept of a Nuclear Weapons Free Zone for the Middle East (MENWFZ).

In calculations of strategic deterrence, Israel's planners must always recall that what matters is whether a prospective attacker perceives secure Israeli retaliatory forces. Where a prospective attacker perceives vulnerable retaliatory forces, it might judge the first-strike option against Israel to be entirely cost-effective. This means, inter alia, that Israel's intelligence estimates must always keep close watch on enemy perceptions, and that when these estimates determine enemy perceptions of Israeli retaliatory force vulnerability, Israel's own preemption option may become more compelling. It also follows, of course, that Israel must always do whatever possible to encourage enemy perceptions of Israeli nuclear force invulnerability, an imperative that could include not only enhanced active defenses, but also, among other things, removing the bomb from the 'basement.'

No discussion of Israeli nuclear deterrence can be complete without careful consideration of the disclosure issue. From the beginning, Israel's bomb has been secluded in the 'basement.' For the future, however, it is by no means certain that an undeclared nuclear deterrent will be capable of meeting Jerusalem's security goals or that it will even be equal in effectiveness to an openly-declared nuclear deterrent. But why? At first glance, the issue appears inconsequential. After all, everyone knows that Israel has the bomb. What, then, would be the purpose of belaboring the obvious? Indeed, might not such unnecessary saber-rattling even be unduly provocative, occasioning Arab and/or Iranian first-strikes that might not otherwise have been contemplated? To respond, we must recall that disclosure would not be intended to reveal the obvious, i.e., that Israel has a bomb, but rather to heighten enemy perceptions of Jerusalem's capable nuclear forces and/or Jerusalem's willingness to use these forces in reprisal for certain first-strike attacks. What, exactly, are the plausible connections between an openly-declared nuclear wepaons capacity and enemy perceptions of Israeli nuclear deterrence? One such connection concerns the relation between disclosure and perceived vulnerability of Israel's nuclear forces to preemptive destruction. Another such connection concerns the relation between disclosure and perceived capacity of Jerusalem's nuclear forces to penetrate the attacking state's active defenses. To the extent that removing the bomb from the basement, or disclosure, would encourage enemy views of an Israeli nuclear force that is sufficiently invulnerable to first-strike attacks and/or is capable of piercing enemy active defense systems, disclosure would represent a rational and prudent option for Israel. Here, the operational benefits of disclosure would accrue from deliberate flows of information about dispersion, multiplication, hardening, speed and evasiveness of nuclear weapon systems and about some other pertinent technical features of certain nuclear weapons. Most importantly, such flows would serve to remove enemy doubts about Israel's nuclear force capabilities, doubts which, left unchallenged, could undermine Israeli nuclear deterrence. Removing the bomb from Israel's basement might also heighten enemy perceptions of Jerusalem's willingness to make good on its nuclear retaliatory threats. For example, by releasing information about its nuclear forces that identifies distinctly usable forces, Israel could remove any doubts about Jerusalem's nuclear resolve. Here, a prospective attacker, newly aware that Israel could retaliate without generating intolerably high levels of civilian harms (possibly because of enhanced radiation and/or sub-kiloton weapons) would be more apt, because of Jerusalem's disclosure, to believe Israel's nuclear threats.

An interesting question arises! To what extent, if any, would Israel's removal of the bomb from the basement affect its inclination to abandon nuclear deterrence in favor of prompt preemption? An antecedent question asks the following: To what extent, if any, might transformation of the territories into 'Palestine' encourage such removal? For the moment, Israel, still buffered somewhat from a hot eastern border, can possibly better afford to keep its bomb in the basement. When, however, this territory becomes Palestine, Israel will almost surely feel compelled to move from 'deliberate ambiguity' to disclosure, a shift that could substantially improve the Jewish State's nuclear deterrence posture, but could also enlarge the chances of a nuclear war should this posture fail.

The importance of 'usable' nuclear weapons must be examined from the standpoint of probable harms. Should Israel's nuclear weapons be perceived by would-be attackers as very high-yield, indiscriminate, 'city-busting' (countervalue) weapons, rather than minimal-yield, warfighting (counterforce) weapons, they might not deter. Contrary to the uninformed conventional wisdom on the subject, successful nuclear deterrence may actually vary inversely with perceived destructiveness. Israeli nuclear deterrence requires not only secure second-strike forces, but also forces that could be reasonably used in war.

Israel's enemies might be judged irrational, but this does not necessarily mean that they are 'crazy.' Indeed, Israeli nuclear deterrence could be immobilized by enemy behavior that is entirely rational, but reflective of what would ordinarily be construed as a fanatical preference ordering. For example, Iran could conceivably act upon a preference ordering that values the destruction of the Jewish State and the fulfillment of presumed Islamic expectations more highly than any other value or combination of values. Here Iran would neither be irrational nor crazy.

Truly, reading the daily accounts of genocide in Rwanda, one loses altogether the distinction between sane and crazy. For the most part, the perpetrators of this genocide, like virtually all genociders in history, are perfectly sane. Perhaps this suggests that Israeli planners would do best to draw their strategic theories and inferences from the genre of the absurd, from the 'preposterous' theater of Beckett, Ionesco, Adamov, Genet and Albee. Can Israel endure in a sane world?

I am thinking about the apparent contradiction between Herman Kahn and Yehoshafat Harkabi. Kahn, in his THINKING ABOUT THE UNTHINKABLE IN THE 1980s, says 'It is unacceptable, in terms of national security, to make nonuse of nuclear weapons the highest national priority to which all other considerations must be subordinated. It is immoral from almost any point of view to refuse to defend yourself and others from very grave and terrible threats....' Harkabi, in THE BAR KOKHBA SYNDROME, draws this 'operative guidance' from the Bar Kokhba Rebellion: 'In choosing a style of fighting, be wary of warfare in which the reaction required of the enemy, from the enemy's point of view, may lead to an action detrimental for you. ...This is an important lesson in nuclear circumstances: refrain from a provocation for which the adversary may have only one response, nuclear war.' The contradiction arises because Kahn demands a willingness to maintain the nuclear option while Harkabi sees just such willingness, inter alia, as an invitation to disaster (as 'unrealistic'). The contradiction would disappear if it could be assumed that nuclear weapons use by Israel would not provoke nuclear war, but this would happen only if Israel's pertinent enemy were non-nuclear or lacked second-strike capability. Also, Kahn speaks of nuclear weapons in terms of 'defense,' a reference that could make sense within the context of certain ATBM systems, but that strays from the more usual context of deterrence. Depending upon the breadth of Kahn's meaning of defense, the contradiction with Harkabi will be more or less substantial.

Elsewhere Harkabi is virtually incoherent. At one point he argues as follows: 'The nuclear era thus generates terminal situations for decision making (emphasis in original). But the mutuality of threat and of destiny moderates the situation and perhaps will, over the course of years, prevent nuclear war.' Why 'mutuality?' Whose 'destiny?' What evidence for 'moderation?' Such anti-thought dramatizes the requirement for a new strategic dialectic.

Harkabi's marked descent into incorrect reasoning continues. Consider the following: 'Nuclear war is absurd, for no national gain could offset the damage such a war would cause. What is the point in attempting to keep a certain asset by threatening to use nuclear weapons, if, as a result of their use, all assets will be lost? The threat to launch a nuclear war is not reasonable, and, thus, not credible. The threat is nevertheless effective because there inheres a residue of doubt that, despite its irrationality, it may be carried out. These contradictions become even more severe, for, even if nuclear war is absurd, it is not absurd for the nuclear powers to plan for such warfare. That is, the preparation of the means to realize the absurd is not absurd. These difficulties lead to a situation where the great powers today are unsuccessful in developing for themselves cohesive doctrines of nuclear strategy, for the absurdity of nuclear war spills over into the extravagances of the strategy of such warfare.' It is difficult to imagine a more incoherent elucidation of nuclear strategy and nuclear war. Not only are the separate components of the 'argument' intrinsically (and prima facie) wrong, they invalidate one another.

I return, again and again, to Eugene Ionesco, the Rumanian-born playwright whose journal, PRESENT PAST/PAST PRESENT: A PERSONAL MEMOIR, bears comparison with Pascal's PENSEES. In July 1967 he permitted himself this important observation: '...in the end, very few people accord the state of Israel the right to exist. This country bothers everybody: it bothers the Russians, it bothers the Americans, it bothers the French...it bothers the Jews who must take a stand...it bothers everybody because the existence of something strong, powerful, unarguable always creates insoluble problems.' Shall Israel become less of a 'bother?' I hope not!

'We are often asked,' said the late Italian Jew and survivor Primo Levi in THE DROWNED AND THE SAVED, 'as if our past conferred a prophetic ability upon us, whether Auschwitz will return....' However we choose to answer so terrible but unavoidable a question, our past seems to have conferred precious little in the way of prophetic abilities. On the contrary, by persistently deluding ourselves that not seeing is a way of not knowing, we have distanced ourselves from the most indispensable forms of warning. Israel take notice.

Israel is macrocosm. Like the individual Jew surrounded by mobs of would- be murderers, the Jewish State stands encircled among a crowd of other states that cries fervently for its extinction. Where it stands stubbornly and defiantly for survivial, the diaspora Jew will have a proud and unparalleled incentive to endure. And wherever the dispora Jew chooses to endure, Israel will be prodded to face its own precarious future with open eyes.

Jews don't like to be bearers of harm; until now, we have been victims rather than executioners. But much as we should like to be 'neither victims nor executioners' (to borrow a phrase again from Albert Camus's essay of the same name), this is simply not possible. The will to mass murder of Jews, as we have learned from so many for so long, is unimpressed by persistent expressions of Jewish goodness. It follows, regarding both Israel and the diaspora, that Jewish 'executioners' have their rightful place and that without this place there would be not diminished pain, but only whole legions of new Jewish and non-Jewish sufferers.



--------------------------------------------------------------------------------



Louis Rene Beres (Ph.D., Princeton, 1971), Professor, Department of Political Science, Purdue University, lectures and publishes widely on Israeli strategic matters. His work is well-known to Israel's military and academic communities. He is also the academic adviser at the Freeman Center for Strategic Studies, a Houston-based research facility and political action group.
reply by
*** This field must be completed **
4/20/2002 (9:02)
 reply top
You're right. I shouldn't have said 'attack'...rather go back to the settlements and the check points and the roads zigzagging through the palestinians homes. And then the palestinians would start the whole suicide bombing again. And Israel would reelect Sharon and then they would bomb Palestine. All I'm saying is give peace a chance. I'm not suggesting that Israel bomb palestine: they WILL bomb palestine if that happened in that scenario.
reply by
carol
4/20/2002 (12:11)
 reply top
oops...this answer is meant for watcher in another post. Sorry..I've only had a few hours of sleep.

As for the above...well, that took over an hour to read. But it gives a picture of Israel as having to be in survival mode for fear of being taken out if they relax for a second. I don't know but after reading most of these posts...one would have to think that the Israelis are right...someone hates them and is after them and for self survival they must be ready in more ways than one. And one of those ways is to strike and strike hard. Is it possible that Israel is preempting with a little too much force. Is Palestine the scapegoat to warn other countries?

Thanks for the article. It has helped me to understand the Israeli side better.Now if I can hold the two sides in question in equal balance without taking a side one way or the other...what is that called, oh yes, 'negative capabilities'...one of those romantic poets of the nineteenth century.., and then on top of that add the opinions and realities of the rest of the world...I'll be in a perfect position to have no opinion at all. I'll go back to my original premises. Each individual, separate from his country, religion, heritage...must make up their minds how they want to live and then take steps to live that life. If the Israelis want to be a part of this latest massacre their government has accomplished, they stay. If the palestinians want to be a part of the suicide bombings and all that infers, they stay. Both of the peoples realising that what they choose to do may effect the whole world in a very unpleasant fashion. But if it leads to the end of civilization as we know it...maybe we can get back to good old family values...foraging for food in the forest, building fires outdoors to keep warm. Braving the elements, hoping for lots of rain in the summer so we can eat in the winter.

Aside from all the possible sores all over our bodies...at least we won't have telephones ringing all the time, or have to watch 'I love lucy' reruns or thank god, no more fricking commercials. And we won't have to wait in lines at the grocery cause there won't be any grocery and there won't be any cars to get there anyway...so we get to walk everywhere and we get healthier. No fricking insurance companies, no fricking drug companies selling us drugs to make us sick so they can sell us more drugs to make us sicker.
reply by
Seth Sims
4/20/2002 (16:12)
 reply top
Carol - Kudos to you for reading through all that material. Most folks up here ignore anything that doesn't agree with their opinion. You are correct in noting that not only will Israel, Palestine, and the neighboring countries be destroyed, but so will much of the rest of the world in many ways.

It is perfectly appropriate to sympathize with the plight of innocent Palestinian civillians, but the blame should be less on the Israelis and more on the leaders of the Palestinians who seek to destroy Israel.
reply by
AngloSaxon
4/21/2002 (1:59)
 reply top
'Demolishing the homes of Arab civilians... Shooting handcuffed prisoners... Forcing local Arabs to test areas where mines may have been planted...'

These sound like the sort of accusations made by British and other European officials concerning Israel's recent actions in Jenin. In fact, they are descriptions from official British documents concerning the methods used by the British authorities to combat Palestinian Arab terrorism in Jenin and elsewhere in 1938.

The documents were declassified by London in 1989. They provide details of the British Mandatory government's response to the assassination of a British district commissioner by a Palestinian Arab terrorist in Jenin in the summer of 1938.

Even after the suspected assassin was captured (and then shot dead while allegedly trying to escape), the British authorities decided that 'a large portion of the town should be blown up' as punishment. On August 25 of that year, a British convoy brought 4,200 kilos of explosives to Jenin for that purpose.

In the Jenin operation and on other occasions, local Arabs were forced to drive 'mine-sweeping taxis' ahead of British vehicles in areas where Palestinian Arab terrorists were believed to have planted mines, in order 'to reduce [British] landmine casualties.'

The British authorities frequently used these and similar methods to combat Palestinian Arab terrorism in the late 1930s.

BRITISH forces responded to the presence of terrorists in the Arab village of Miar, north of Haifa, by blowing up house after house in October 1938.

'When the troops left, there was little else remaining of the once-busy village except a pile of mangled masonry,' The New York Times reported.

The declassified documents refer to an incident in Jaffa in which a handcuffed prisoner was shot by the British police.

Under Emergency Regulation 19b, the British Mandate government could demolish any house located in a village where terrorists resided, even if that particular house had no direct connection to terrorist activity. Mandate official Hugh Foot later recalled: 'When we thought that a village was harboring rebels, we'd go there and mark one of the large houses. Then, if an incident was traced to that village, we'd blow up the house we'd marked.'

The High Commissioner for Palestine, Harold MacMichael, defended the practice: 'The provision is drastic, but the situation has demanded drastic powers.'

MacMichael was furious over what he called the 'grossly exaggerated accusations' that England's critics were circulating concerning British anti-terror tactics in Palestine. Arab allegations that British soldiers gouged out the eyes of Arab prisoners were quoted prominently in the Nazi German press and elsewhere.

The declassified documents also record discussions among officials of the Colonial Office concerning the rightness or wrongness of the anti-terror methods used in Palestine. Lord Dufferin remarked: 'British lives are being lost and I don't think that we, from the security of Whitehall, can protest squeamishly about measures taken by the men in the frontline.'

Sir John Shuckburgh defended the tactics on the grounds that the British were confronted 'not with a chivalrous opponent playing the game according to the rules, but with gangsters and murderers.'

There were many differences between British policy in the 1930s and Israeli policy today, but one stands out - the British, faced with a level of Palestinian Arab terrorism considerably less lethal than that which Israel faces today, utilized anti-terror methods considerably harsher than those used by Israeli forces.
reply by
carol
4/21/2002 (4:34)
 reply top
There must be some elderly people in Jenin who remember this. Would be very interesting to know what they are thinking.